Gebruiker:Phidias/Kladblok/Vertaalpagina2

Phidias Overleg Scriptorium Mijn Bijdragen Projecten Portaal Filosofie Wikiproject Filosofie
Kladblok Vertaalpagina 1 Vertaalpagina 2 Vertaalpagina 3 Werkplaats
Gegroet!
  • Dit is een subpagina van de kladblok van Phidias. Deze pagina is bedoeld voor vertalingen van grote artikels waarvoor geen plaats is op de primaire kladblok-pagina. Tenzij anders aangegeven valt de inhoud van deze pagina uitdrukkelijk niet onder het publiek domein!

Peter Singer bewerken

 
Peter Singer

Peter Albert David Singer (6 juli 1946, Melbourne, Australië - ) is een Australische filosoof. Hij is Ira W. DeCamp professor in de bio-ethiek aan de Princeton University en tevens laureaat professor aan het departement voor Applied Philosophy and Public Ethics van de University of Melbourne. Singer is gespecialiseerd in de toegepaste ethiek en is een vertegenwoordiger van het Preferentie-utilitarisme.

Biografie bewerken

Singers ouders waren Weense joden die Oostenrijk ontvlucht hadden in 1938 en toevlucht zochten in Australië. Zijn vader was een importeur van koffie en thee en zijn moeder was arts van beroep. Singer zelf studeerde rechten, geschiedenis en filosofie aan de University of Melbourne, waar hij afstudeerde in 1967. In 1969 werd hij gepromoveerd na het schrijven van een verhandeling getiteld "Why should I be moral?. Hij kreeg een beurs aangeboden om te gaan studeren aan Oxford University in het Verenigd Koninkrijk, waar hij een Bachelor-graad behaalde in de wijsbegeerte in 1971, met zijn verhandeling over publieke ongehoorzaamheid. Deze verhandeling werd gemaakt onder begeleiding van de bekende moraalfilosoof R. M. Hare en werd in boekvorm uitgegeven in 1973 onder de titel "Democracy and disobedience".[1]

Na twee jaar als docent aan de University College, Oxford, was hij gedurende 16 maanden gastdocent aan de New York University. Hij keerde terug naar Melbourne in 1977 waar hij de komende 20 jaar van zijn leven zou doorbrengen, uitgezonderd tijdelijke aanstellingen als gastdocent aan vele buitenlandse universiteiten. In 1999 verhuisde hij uiteindelijk naar Princeton. In 1996 was hij kandidaat voor de senaat van Australië op de lijst van Australische groene partij. Hij werd niet verkozen. In 2004 werd hij onderscheiden als humanist van het jaar door de Council of Australian Humanist Societies.

Buiten de academische wereld is Singer vooral bekend omwille van zijn boek Animal liberation (1976), dat nog steeds gezien wordt als een basiswerk voor de dierenrechtenbeweging. Singer is ook één van de grondleggers van het Great Ape Project, een oranisatie die als doel heeft de Verenigde Naties er van te overtuigen grote aapachtigen te erkennen als personen.

Animal liberation bewerken

Singer's boek Animal Liberation[2] werd gepubliceerd in 1975 en heeft een belangrijke invloed uitgeoefend bij de vorming van de huidige dierenrechtenbeweging. Hoewel Siger zich verzet tegen de gedachte rechten te zien als ideaal naast zijn Utilitaristische theorie, gebaseerd op belangen, aanvaard hij rechten wel als afgeleide principes van utilitaristische principes, vooral het streven naar een minimalisering van het lijden in de wereld.[3] Singer wijst er wel op dat de rechten van dieren niet exact hetzelfde zijn als die van mensen. In Animal liberation schrijft hij dat er duidelijk belangrijke verschillen zijn tussen de mens en andere diersoorten en dat deze verschillen resulteren in het toekennen van verschillende rechten.[4] Zo heeft bijvoorbeeld een dier geen recht op gedegen onderwijs, aangezien dit voor hen volkomen betekenisloos is, net zoals een recht op abortus betekenisloos is voor een man. Singer staat echter niet meer sceptisch ten aanzien van dierenrechten dan hij sceptisch is ten aanzien van vrouwenrechten. Hij begint zijn boek met een verdediging van deze vergelijking gericht tegen Thomas Taylor, een 18e eeuwse criticus van Mary Wollstonecraft, die stelde dat indien de redenering van Wollstonecraft correct was, dit zou impliceren dat ook 'barbaren' rechten zouden hebben. Taylor meende hiermee een reductio ad absurdum te hebben afgeleid uit Wollstonecraft's argumentatie. Singer beschouwt het echter als een correcte logische implicatie. Taylor's modus tollens wordt met andere woorden bij Singer de modus ponens van de redenering.

In Animal Liberation pleit Singer tegen wat hij Speciecisme noemt: Discriminatie op basis van het al dan niet behoren tot een bepaalde soort. Hij verdedigt zelf dat de belangen van alle wezens die het vermogen hebben om te lijden, in aanmerking komen voor gelijke behandeling en dat het minderwaardig behandelen van bepaalde levende wezens, enkel en alleen omwille van het feit dat ze vleugels of een vacht hebben, niet meer gerechtvaardigd is dan discriminatie op basis van bijvoorbeeld huidskleur. In het bijzonder argumenteert Singer dat, hoewel dieren over een lagere intelligentie beschikken dan de gemiddelde menselijke persoon, veel ernstig mentaal gehandicapte mensen een zelfde lager intellectueel vermogen vertonen, waardoor intelligentie niet kan fungeren als basis voor de legitimatie van een ongelijke behandeling van dieren ten aanzien van mensen. Hij besluit dat het gebruik van dieren als voedsel voor de mens onverantwoordbaar is, aangezien het onnodig lijden teweeg brengt. Zelf beschouwt hij het veganisme als het meest verantwoorde dieet. Singer verwerpt ook de meeste vormen van vivisectie, hoewel hij van mening is dat bepaalde experimenten op dieren toegestaan kunnen worden, indien de voordelen (in de zin van bijvoorbeeld de verbetering van medische behandelingen, etc.) groter zijn dan de schade die aan de dieren wordt toegebracht. Aangezien de term 'voordelen' in zekere zin erg subjectief is, bestaat er op dit punt discussie met andere strekkingen van het utilitarisme. Singer stelt echter wel duidelijk dat mensen met vergelijkbaar bewustzijn ook kandidaten zouden moeten zijn voor elk van zulke experimenten dat in overeenstemming met het voordeel-criterium. Op die manier zijn een aap en een mensenkind in gelijke omstandigheden vanuit moreel oogpunt in dezelfde mate geschikt voor een experiment. Wanneer het uitvoeren van een experiment op een kind ontoelaatbaar wordt beschouwd, dan is Singer van mening dat het experiment beter helemaal niet wordt uitgevoerd, dus ook niet bij dieren. In plaats daarvan zouden onderzoekers ernaar moeten streven hun doelstellingen te bereiken door gebruik te maken van computersimulaties of via andere wegen. Aanvaarbare vivisectie zou zwak speciecistisch zijn in zoverre dat het geen rekening zou houden met de belangen van menselijke kandidaten over niet-menselijke kandidaten, maar waarschijnlijk zou in dergelijke gevallen het lidmaatschap van de soort als een geldig criterium kunnen gebruikt worden, wanneer alle andere relevante aspecten gelijk lopen.

Applied ethics bewerken

His most comprehensive work, Practical Ethics,[5] analyses in detail why and how beings' interests should be weighed. His principle of equality encompasses all beings with interests, and it requires equal consideration of those interests, whatever the species. The principle of equal consideration of interests does not dictate equal treatment of all those with interests, since different interests warrant different treatment. All have an interest in avoiding pain, for instance, but relatively few have an interest in cultivating their abilities. Not only does his principle justify different treatment for different interests, but it allows different treatment for the same interest when diminishing marginal utility is a factor, favoring (say) a starving person's interest in food over the same interest of someone who is only slightly hungry.

Among the more important human interests are those in avoiding pain, in developing one's abilities, in satisfying basic needs for food and shelter, in enjoying warm personal relationships, in being free to pursue one's projects without interference, "and many others". The fundamental interest that entitles a being to equal consideration is the capacity for "suffering and/or enjoyment or happiness"; mice as well as human beings have this interest, but stones and trees do not. He holds that a being's interests should always be weighed according to that being's concrete properties, and not according to its belonging to some abstract group such as a species, or a set of possible beings, or an early stage of something with an as yet unactualized potential. He favors a 'journey' model of life, which measures the wrongness of taking a life by the degree to which doing so frustrates a life journey's goals. So taking a life is less wrong at the beginning, when no goals have been set, and at the end, when the goals have either been met or are unlikely to be accomplished. The journey model is tolerant of some frustrated desire, explains why persons who have embarked on their journeys are not replaceable, and accounts for why it is wrong to bring a miserable life into existence. Although sentience puts a being within the sphere of equal consideration of interests, only a personal interest in continuing to live brings the journey model into play. This model also explains the priority that Singer attaches to interests over trivial desires and pleasures. For instance, one has an interest in food, but not in the pleasures of the palate that might distinguish eating steak from eating tofu, because nutrition is instrumental to many goals in one's life journey, whereas the desire for meat is not and is therefore trumped by the interest of animals in avoiding the miseries of factory farming.

In order to avoid bias towards human interests, he requires the idea of an impartial standpoint from which to compare interests. This is an elaboration of the familiar idea of putting oneself in the other's shoes, adjusted for beings with paws or flippers. He has wavered about whether the precise aim is the total amount of satisfied interests, or instead the most satisfied interests among those beings who already exist prior to the decision one is making. Both have liabilities. The total view, for instance, seems to lead to Derek Parfit's Repugnant Conclusion[6] -- that is, it seems to imply that it's morally better to have an enormous population with lives barely worth living rather than a smaller population with much happier lives. The prior-existence view, on the other hand, seems questionably indifferent to the harm or benefit one can do to those who are brought into existence by one's decisions. The second edition of Practical Ethics disavows the first edition's suggestion that the total and prior-existence views should be combined in such a way that the total view applies to sentient beings who are not self-conscious and the prior-existence view applies to those who are. This would mean that rats and human infants are replaceable -- their painless death is permissible as long as they are replaced -- whereas human adults and other persons in Singer's expanded sense, including great apes, are not replaceable. The second edition dispenses with the requirement of replacement and the consequent high population numbers for sentient beings. It asserts that preference-satisfaction utilitarianism, incorporating the 'journey' model, applies without invoking the first edition's suggestion about the total view. But the details are fuzzy and Singer admits that he is "not entirely satisfied" with his treatment of choices that involve bringing beings into existence.

Ethical conduct is justifiable by reasons that go beyond prudence to "something bigger than the individual," addressing a larger audience. Singer thinks this going-beyond identifies moral reasons as "somehow universal", specifically in the injunction to 'love thy neighbor as thyself', interpreted by him as demanding that one give the same weight to the interests of others as one gives to one's own interests. This universalizing step, which Singer traces from Kant to Hare, is crucial and sets him apart from moral theorists from Hobbes to David Gauthier, who regard that step as flatly irrational. Universalization leads directly to utilitarianism, Singer argues, on the strength of the thought that my own interests cannot count for more than the interests of others. Taking these into account, one must weigh them up and adopt the course of action that is most likely to maximize the interests of those affected; utilitarianism has been arrived at. Singer's universalizing step applies to interests without reference to who has them, whereas a kantian's applies to the judgments of rational agents (in Kant's kingdom of ends, or Rawls's Original Position, etc.). Singer regards kantian universalization as unjust to animals. It's their capacity for suffering/happiness that matters morally, not their deficiency with respect to rational judgment. As for the hobbesians, Singer attempts a response in the final chapter of Practical Ethics, arguing that self-interested reasons support adoption of the moral point of view, such as 'the paradox of hedonism', which counsels that happiness is best found by not looking for it, and the need most people feel to relate to something larger than their own concerns.

Abortion, euthanasia and infanticide bewerken

Consistent with his general ethical theory, Singer holds that the right to physical integrity is grounded in a being's ability to suffer, and the right to life is grounded in, among other things, the ability to plan and anticipate one's future. Since the unborn, infants and severely disabled people lack the latter (but not the former) ability, he states that abortion, painless infanticide and euthanasia can be justified in certain special circumstances, for instance in the case of severely disabled infants whose life would cause suffering both to themselves and to their parents.

In his view the central argument against abortion is It is wrong to kill an innocent human being; a human fetus is an innocent human being; therefore it is wrong to kill a human fetus. He challenges the first premise, on the grounds that its reference to human beings is ambiguous as between human beings in the zoological sense and persons as rational and self-conscious. There is no sanctity of human life that confers moral protection on human beings in the zoological sense. Until the capacity for pain develops after "18 weeks of gestation", abortion terminates an existence that has no intrinsic value (as opposed to the value it might have in virtue of being valued by the parents or others). As it develops the features of a person, it has moral protections that are comparable to those that should be extended to nonhuman life as well. He also rejects a backup argument against abortion that appeals to potential: It is wrong to kill a potential human being; a human fetus is a potential human being; therefore it is wrong to kill a human fetus. The second premise is more plausible, but its first premise is less plausible, and Singer denies that a potential X has the same value or moral rights as an X. Against those who stress the continuity of our existence from conception to adulthood, he poses the example of an embryo in a dish on a laboratory bench, which he calls Mary. Now if it divides into two identical embryos, there is no way to answer the question whether Mary dies, or continues to exist, or is replaced by Jane and Susan. These are absurd questions, he thinks, and their absurdity casts doubt on the view that the embryo is a human being in the morally significant sense.

Singer classifies euthanasia as voluntary, involuntary, or non-voluntary. (For possible similar historical definitions of euthanasia see Karl Binding, Alfred Hoche and Werner Catel.) Given his consequentialist approach, the difference between active and passive euthanasia is not morally significant, for the required act/omission doctrine is untenable; killing and letting die are on a moral par when their consequences are the same. Voluntary euthanasia, undertaken with the consent of the subject, is supported by the autonomy of persons and their freedom to waive their rights, especially against a legal background such as the guidelines developed by the courts in the Netherlands. Non-voluntary euthanasia at the beginning or end of life's journey, when the capacity to reason about what is at stake is undeveloped or lost, is justified when swift and painless killing is the only alternative to suffering for the subject.

World poverty bewerken

In "Famine, Affluence, and Morality",[7] one of Singer's best-known philosophical essays, he argues that the injustice of some people living in abundance while others starve is morally indefensible. Singer proposes that anyone able to help the poor should donate part of their income to aid poverty and similar efforts. Singer reasons that, when one is already living comfortably, a further purchase to increase comfort will lack the same moral importance as saving another person's life. Singer himself donates 20% of his salary to Oxfam and Unicef. In "Rich and Poor", the version of the aforementioned article that appears in the second edition of Practical Ethics,[8] his main argument is presented as follows: If we can prevent something bad without sacrificing anything of comparable significance, we ought to do it; absolute poverty is bad; there is some poverty we can prevent without sacrificing anything of comparable moral significance; therefore we ought to prevent some absolute poverty.

Other views bewerken

Zoophilia bewerken

In a 2001 review of Midas Dekkers's Dearest Pet: On Bestiality,[9] Singer stated that "mutually satisfying activities" of a sexual nature may sometimes occur between humans and animals and that writer Otto Soyka would condone such activities. Singer states that Dekkers believes that Zoophilia should remain illegal if it involves what he sees as "cruelty", but otherwise is no cause for shock or horror. Singer believes that although sex between species is not normal or natural, it does not constitute a transgression of our status as human beings, because human beings are animals or, more specifically, we are great apes. Religious groups, animal rights groups, and others have condemned this view, while animal rights organization PETA has supported them.[10]

Immigratie bewerken

Singer is van mening dat welvarende landen de plicht hebben om veel meer vluchtelingen op te nemen dan nu het geval is. Hij stelt daarom voor dat dergelijke landen beginnen met een jaarlijkse verdubbeling van de migratiequota's en dit aanhoudt tot men op een niveau gekomen is waarbij verdere immigratie globaal gezien meer slecht dan goed zal doen.

The Natural Environment bewerken

As the natural world is not sentient, Singer claims it has no intrinsic value. However, he says that the value to present and future sentient beings of maintaining the environment is so high that people and their governments should make drastic changes to their way of life to ensure the world's preservation.

Evolutionary Biology and Liberal Politics bewerken

In A Darwinian Left,[11] Singer outlines a plan for the political left to adapt to the lessons of Darwinism and evolutionary biology. He says that evolutionary psychology suggests that humans naturally tend to be self-interested, and that leftists can't ignore scientific fact simply because it's unpleasant or inconvenient for achieving their political goals. He further argues that the evidence that selfish tendencies are natural must not be taken as evidence that selfishness is right. He concludes that game theory (the mathematical study of strategy) and experiments in psychology offer hope that self-interested people will make short-term sacrifices for the good of others, if society provides the right conditions. Essentially Singer claims that although humans possess selfish, competitive tendencies naturally, they have a substantial capacity for cooperation that has also been selected for by evolution. It's the job of the Left, he says, to create those conditions which foster cooperation amongst members of society.

Criticism bewerken

Singer's positions have been attacked by many different groups concerned with what they see as an attack upon human dignity, from advocates for disabled people to religious groups, including right-to-life supporters.

Critics argue that Singer is in no position to judge the quality of life of disabled people. In Germany, his position has been compared to the Nazi practice of murdering "unworthy life", and his lectures have been repeatedly disrupted. Some claim that Singer's utilitarian ideas lead to eugenics. Nazi-hunter Simon Wiesenthal wrote to organizers of a Swedish book fair to which Singer was invited that "A professor of morals ... who justifies the right to kill handicapped newborns ... is in my opinion unacceptable for representation at your level."[12] Singer's conclusions in controversial areas such as abortion, infanticide and euthanasia may help explain why his works have attracted particular attention.

Some commentators expressed their disapproval at the publication of Singer's review essay in which he discusses bestiality as a logical conclusion to some of the arguments he has made with respect to the relationship of humans to animals.[13]

Proponents of other ethical systems like deontology or virtue ethics have found in Singer's work ammunition against utilitarianism and its consequentialism (that is, its assumption that the morality of an act is to be evaluated according to its consequences). They claim that his conclusions show that utilitarianism may lead to eugenics, infanticide, or even justification of torture[bron?] in certain circumstances.

Singer has replied that many people judge him based on secondhand summaries and short quotations taken out of context, not his books or articles. For example, when people hear that Singer thinks that a dog has the same moral importance as a newborn baby, they might interpret the statement as dehumanising, because of the low value traditionally placed on the interests of animals. However, although Singer does not regard the newborn child as deserving the same degree of consideration as an adult, he regards animals as deserving a much higher degree of consideration than they have traditionally been given.[14]

Singer experienced the complexities of some of these questions in his own life. Singer's mother had Alzheimer's disease, which rendered her, in Singer's system, a "nonperson". He did not euthanise her, saying, "I think this has made me see how the issues of someone with these kinds of problems are really very difficult".[15] In an interview with Ronald Bailey published in December 2000 he explained that he is not the only person who is involved in making decisions about his mother (he has a sister). He did say that if he were solely responsible, his mother might not be alive today.[16] (Singer's mother died shortly thereafter.) This incident has led to accusations of hypocrisy. However, Singer has never argued that a non-person who is not suffering has to be euthanised - only that it could be morally acceptable to euthanise.

Meta-ethics and foundational issues bewerken

Though Singer focuses more than many philosophers on applied ethical questions, he has also written in depth on foundational issues in meta-ethics, including why one ethical system should be chosen over others. In The Expanding Circle,[17] he argues that that the evolution of human society provides support for the utilitarian point of view. On his account, ethical reasoning has existed from the time primitive foraging bands had to cooperate, compromise, and make group decisions to survive. He elaborates: "In a dispute between members of a cohesive group of reasoning beings, the demand for a reason is a demand for a justification that can be accepted by the group as a whole."{{Citation needed}} Thus, consideration of others' interests has long been a necessary part of the human experience. Singer believes that contemplative analysis may now guide one to accept a broader utilitarianism:

If I have seen that from an ethical point of view I am just one person among the many in my society, and my interests are no more important, from the point of view of the whole, than the similar interests of others within my society, I am ready to see that, from a still larger point of view, my society is just one among other societies, and the interests of members of my society are no more important, from that larger perspective, than the similar interests of members of other societies… Taking the impartial element in ethical reasoning to its logical conclusion means, first, accepting that we ought to have equal concern for all human beings.{{Citation needed}}

Singer elaborates that viewing oneself as equal to others in one's society and at the same time viewing one's society as fundamentally superior to other societies may cause an uncomfortable cognitive dissonance. This is the sense in which he means that reason may push people to accept a broader utilitarian stance. Critics like Ken Binmore point out that this cognitive dissonance is apparently not very strong, since people often knowingly ignore the interests of faraway societies quite similar to their own.[18] They also argue that the "ought" of the quoted paragraph applies only to someone who has already accepted the premise that all socities are equally important. Singer has responded that his argument in Expanding the Circle wasn't intended to provide a complete philosophical justification for a utilitarian categorical imperative, but merely to provide a plausible explanation for how some people come to accept utilitarianism.

An alternative line taken by Singer about the need for ethics[19] is that living the ethical life may be, on the whole, more satisfying than seeking only material gain. He invokes the hedonistic paradox, noting that those who pursue material gain seldom find the happiness they seek. Having a broader purpose in life may lead to more long-term happiness. On this account, impartial (self-sacrificing) behavior in particular matters may be motivated by self-interested considerations from a broader perspective. This argument does not justify utilitarianism in particular as opposed to other ethical philosophies; instead, it defends the need for ethics in general.

Singer has also implicitly argued that a watertight defense of utilitarianism is not crucial to his work. In "Famine, Affluence, and Morality", he begins by saying that he would like to see how far a seemingly innocuous and widely endorsed principle can take us; the principle is that one is morally required to forego a small pleasure to relieve someone else's immense pain. He then argues that this principle entails radical conclusions – for example, that most Americans are extremely immoral for not giving up some luxury goods in order to donate the money for famine relief. If his reasoning is valid, either it is not immoral to value small luxuries over saving many lives, or many Americans are very immoral. From this perspective, regardless of the soundness of Singer's fundamental defense of utilitarianism, his work has value in that it exposes conflicts between many people's stated beliefs and their actions.

Publications bewerken

Some of his other publications include:

  • The Way We Eat : Why Our Food Choices Matter, 2006 (with Jim Mason)
  • The President of Good & Evil, the Ethics of George W. Bush, 2004
  • Pushing Time Away : My Grandfather and the Tragedy of Jewish Vienna, 2003
  • One World: The Ethics of Globalization, 2002
  • Rethinking Life and Death : The Collapse of Our Traditional Ethics, 1996
  • How Are We to Live?: Ethics in an Age of Self-Interest, 1993
  • Should the Baby Live?, 1985

See also bewerken

Referenties bewerken

  1. Democracy and Disobedience, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1973, ISBN 0198245041.
  2. Animal Liberation: A New Ethics for our Treatment of Animals, New York: New York review/Random House, 1975, ISBN 0394400968; second edition, 1990, ISBN 0940322005.
  3. Vergelijk dit standpunt met dat van John Stuart Mill, één van de grondleggers van het utilitarisme, wiens verdediging van individuele rechten in On liberty (1859) ingeleid wordt met de volgende kwalificatie: "It is proper to state that I forego any advantage which could be derived to my argument from the idea of abstract right as a thing independent of utility".
  4. Op. cit., p. 2.
  5. Practical Ethics, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1979, ISBN 0521229200; second edition, 1993, ISBN 0521433630.
  6. See Derek Parfit, Reasons and Persons, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984, .
  7. "Famine, Affluence, and Morality"Philosophy and Public Affairs, vol. 1, no. 1 (Spring 1972), pp. 229-243.
  8. Op. cit., pp. 218-246.
  9. "Heavy Petting", Nerve, March 2001; Heavy Petting", Prospect, April 2001, pp. 12-13.
  10. Sarah Boxer, "Yes, but Did Anyone Ask the Animals' Opinion?", The New York Times, June 9, 2001.
  11. A Darwinian Left: Politics, Evolution, and Cooperation, New Haven : Yale University Press, 2000, ISBN 0300083238.
  12. Don Felder, "Professor Death will fit right in at Princeton, Jewish World Review, October 28, 1998.
  13. "Animal Crackers", The Wall Street Journal, March 30, 2001.
  14. "[T]he aim of my argument is to elevate the status of animals rather than to lower the status of any humans" (Practical Ethics, p. 77).
  15. Quoted in Michael Specter, "The Dangerous Philosopher", The New Yorker, September 6, 1999.
  16. Ronald Bailey, "The Pursuit of Happiness", Reason (magazine), December 2000.
  17. The Expanding Circle: Ethics and Sociobiology, New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 1981, ISBN 0374234965.
  18. Ken Binmore, Natural Justice, Oxford : Oxford University Press, 2005. ISBN 0195178114.
  19. In, e.g., the last chapter of Practical Ethics.

External links bewerken

Criticism bewerken

[[de:Peter Singer]] [[es:Peter Singer]] [[fr:Peter Singer]] [[it:Peter Singer]] [[he:פיטר סינגר]] [[ja:ピーター・シンガー]] [[no:Peter Singer]] [[pl:Peter Singer]] [[pt:Peter Singer]] [[sk:Peter Singer]] [[fi:Peter Singer]] [[sv:Peter Singer]]